updated and corrections / mise à jour et corrections: 7
September 2009
by / par ©François
Lareau,
2008-, Ottawa, Canada
First placed on the Internet on 2 April 2008
Bibliography actio
libera in causa, prior fault
Bibliographie: actio libera in causa et faute antérieure
AMBOS, Kai, "General Principles of Criminal Law in the Rome
Statute",
(1999) 10(1) Criminal Law Forum 1-32, and see pp. 25-26;
available at http://lehrstuhl.jura.uni-goettingen.de/kambos/Person/doc/General_Principles.pdf
(accessed on 1 April 2008);
THE AMERICAN LAW INSTITUTE, Model Penal Code: Proposed Official
Draft,
Philadelphia:
The American Law Institute, 1962, xxii, 346 p., see section 2.08,
"Intoxication",
p. 38;
BURCHELL, E.M., J.R.L. Milton and J.M. Burchell, South African Criminal Law and Procedure, Vol I, General Principles of Criminal Law by EM Burchell and PMA Hunt, 2nd ed., Cape Town: Juta, 1983, lxii, 512 p., and see "ACTIO LIBERA IN CAUSA", at pp. 291-293, ISBN: 070211345X (hardcover) and 0702113468 (softcover); research note: there is now a 3rd ed., Kenwyn: Juta, 1997, xxxviii, 383 p., (series; South African criminal law and procedure; v. 1), ISBN: 070213855X which I have not consulted;
BURCHELL, Jonathan and John Milton, Principles of Criminal Law,
Cape Town: Juta, 1991,
xlvii,
669 p., and see pp. 80-81, ISBN: 07212639X;
research note: there is now a 2nd ed,
Kenwyn: Juta, 1997, li, 734 p., ISBN: 0702138541 which I have not
consulted yet;
CANADA, Criminal Code, s. 35;
available at http://laws.justice.gc.ca/en/index.html;
Code criminel, article 35,
disponible à http://laws.justice.gc.ca/fr/HOME;
(a) he uses the force
(i) under reasonable apprehension of death or grievous bodily harm from the violence of the person whom he has assaulted or provoked, and
(ii) in the belief, on reasonable grounds, that it is necessary in order to preserve himself from death or grievous bodily harm;
(b) he did not, at any time before the necessity of preserving himself from death or grievous bodily harm arose, endeavour to cause death or grievous bodily harm; and
(c)
he declined further conflict and quitted or retreated from it as far as
it was feasible to do so before the necessity of preserving himself
from death or grievous bodily harm arose. [emphasis in bold added]
Provocation
36.
Provocation includes, for the purposes of sections 34 and 35,
provocation by blows, words or gestures.
------
a) il en fait usage :
(i) d’une part, parce qu’il a des motifs raisonnables d’appréhender que la mort ou des lésions corporelles graves ne résultent de la violence de la personne qu’il a attaquée ou provoquée,
(ii) d’autre part, parce qu’il croit, pour des motifs raisonnables, que la force est nécessaire en vue de se soustraire lui-même à la mort ou à des lésions corporelles graves;
b) il n’a, à aucun moment avant qu’ait surgi la nécessité de se soustraire à la mort ou à des lésions corporelles graves, tenté de causer la mort ou des lésions corporelles graves;
DANDO, Shigemitsu,
1913-, The Criminal Law of Japan: The General Part, Littleton
(Colorado): Fred B. Rothman, 1997, xxiv, 521 p., and see "Acts Free in
Causation", at pp. 77-80
(Series; Publications of the Comparative
Criminal Law Project, vol. 19); limited preview available at http://books.google.com/books?id=gN0QgcW4Td0C&pg=PR17&dq=%22german+criminal+law%22&lr=&as_brr=3&ei=fZvKR-WlBKGyiQGvjrgK&sig=OePFCBqZQ5B-pU7oaj7vYuuszHI and http://books.google.com/books?id=gN0QgcW4Td0C&dq=%22german+criminal+law%22&lr=&as_brr=3&source=gbs_summary_s&cad=0 (accessed on 2 March 2008);
DEGIROLAMI, Marc O., "Culpability in Creating Criminal Necessity" , Alabama Law Review, Vol. 60, forthcoming and available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1115835 (accessed on 3 April 2008);
ESER, "Article 31: Grounds for excluding criminal
responsibility"
in Otto Triffterer, ed., Commentary on the Rome Statute of the
International
Criminal Court: Observers' Notes, Article by Article, Baden Baden:
Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 1999, xxviii, 1295 p. at pp. 537-554, see
"Intoxication"
at pp. 546-548, ISBN: 378906173; copy at the Department of External
Affairs,
Ottawa, call number: legal KZ 6310 .C734 1999; available at http://www.freidok.uni-freiburg.de/volltexte/3922/pdf/Eser_Grounds_for_excluding_criminal_responsibility.pdf
(accessed on 7 March 2008);
FINKELSTEIN, Claire O., and Leo Katz, "Contrived
Defenses and
Deterrent Threats : Two Facets of One Problem",
(Spring 2008) 5(2) Ohio State
Journal of Criminal Law 479-504; available at http://moritzlaw.osu.edu/osjcl/Articles/Volume5_2/FinkelsteinKatzPDF.pdf
(accessed on 23 March 2008); deals with the doctrine actio libera in causa;
GRAVEN, Philippe,L'infraction pénale punissable,
Berne :
Éditions
Staempfli, 1993, xv, 346 p., (Collection; Précis de droit
Staempfli),
ISBN: 372720978X; il y a maintenant une deuxième édition
soit une mise à jour par Bernhard Sträuli, 1995, 376
p.,
ISBN: 3727209836;
GUR-ARYE, Miriam, Actio Libera in Causa in Criminal Law,
Jerusalem : Harry Sacher Institute for Legislative Research and
Comparative
Law, Faculty of Law, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, 1984, 110
p.;
Research
Note: see in particular Chapter 3: "Action Libera in Causa and the
Defences of Duress, Necessity and Private-Defence"; see Table of Contents;
HURTADO POZO, José, Droit pénal -- Partie
générale, 2,
Zurich: Schulthness Polygraphischer Verlag, 2002, xli, 396 p., ISBN:
3725544700
HERMANN, Joachim, "Causing
the Conditions of One's Own Defense: The
Multifaceted Approach of German Law", [1986] Brigham Young
UniversityLaw
Review 747-767; available at http://lawreview.byu.edu/archives/1986/3/her.pdf
(accessed on 24 March 2008); also published in A. Eser et al.,
eds., Justification
and Excuse: Comparative Perspectives, vol. 1, Dobbs Ferry (New
York),
Transnational Juris Publications, 1987, at p. 745, ISBN: 0929179226; important
contribution;
KATZ, Leo, "Before and After: Temporal Anomalies in Legal Doctrine", (2003) 151 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 863-885, at 880-881; vailable at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=347300 or DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.347300 (accessed on 1 April 2008);
KILLIAS, Martin en collaboration avec Bernard A.
Dénéréaz,
Précis
de droit pénal général, Berne: Staempfli,
1998,
xlv, 300 p., (collection; Précis de droit Staempfli),
ISBN:
3727209895; il existe aussi une 2e
édition,
Berne, 2001;
LOGOZ, Paul, 1888-1973, Commentaire du Code pénal
suisse, Partie
Générale,
2e éd. mise à jour avec la collaboration d'Yves Sandoz,
Neuchâtel
: Delachaux & Niestlé, 1976, 569 p., ISBN: 2603000578;
MANNHEIM, Hermann,
1889-, Group problems in crime and
punishment, and other studies in
criminology and criminal law, London, Routledge and Paul [1955],
x, 309
p.( International library of sociology and social reconstruction
(Routledge & Kegan Paul)), and see
pp. 292-296; limited preview available at http://books.google.com/books?id=Yh7pzooWO9EC&pg=PA292&dq=%22actio+libera%22&lr=lang_en&as_brr=0&sig=2QsQLPcQMnz4pbHq5OGSf_KQZD8#PPA292,M1 and http://books.google.com/books?id=Yh7pzooWO9EC&dq=%22actio+libera%22&lr=lang_en&as_brr=0&source=gbs_summary_s&cad=0 (accessed on 1 April 2008);
MITCHELL, Edward H., 1972-, Self-Made
Madness: Rethinking Illness and Criminal Responsibility,
Aldershot (Hants, England)/Burlington (Vt.) : Ashgate, c2003,
xix, 252 p., and see "Robinson's Doctrine of Separate Liability", at
pp. 102-104, ISBN: 0754623327; pages 102-104 are available at http://books.google.com/books?id=fLkrTqPI65UC&pg=PA102&dq=%22+%22Causing+the+
Conditions+of+One%27s+Own+Defense%22&lr=&as_brr=0&ei=KDT3R4_6LJDyiwGot-zyCQ&sig=qsaqhL0KVdemrXb0c_axPP-3cA4 and http://books.google.com/books?id=fLkrTqPI65UC&dq=%22+%22Causing+the+Conditions+of+One's+Own+Defense%22&lr=&as_brr=0&source=gbs_summary_s&cad=0
(accessed on 5 April 2008);
Perka v. The Queen, [1984] 2 S.C.R. 232, available at http://scc.lexum.umontreal.ca/en/1984/1984rcs2-232/1984rcs2-232.html
In Salvador, Jones J.A. cited sources in support of his view that illegal conduct should act as a bar to the necessity defence. These sources do not support that view but do support a closely related notion—that if the accused's own "fault" (including negligence or recklessness) is responsible for, the events giving rise to the necessity, he may not' rely on the necessity defence.
This limitation has found expression in several American state statutes codifying the necessity defence, such as those of New York and Illinois and has been adopted by the United States National Commission on Reform of Federal Criminal Laws which recommended that the defence apply only "where the situation developed through no fault of the actor". A parallel is sometimes drawn between such a limitation and the restrictions placed on the availability of the largely analogous defence of duress. See, e.g., A. J. Ashworth, "Reason, Logic and Criminal Liability", (1975) 91 L.Q.R. 102 at p. 106.
In my view the accused's fault in bringing about the situation later invoked to excuse his conduct can be relevant to the availability of the defence of necessity, but not in the sweeping way suggested by some of the commentators and in some of the statutory formulations. Insofar as the accused's "fault" reflects on the moral quality of the action taken to meet the emergency, it is irrelevant to the issue of the availability of the defence on the same basis as the illegality or immorality of the actions preceding the emergency are irrelevant. If this fault is capable of attracting criminal or civil liability in its own right, the culprit should be
appropriately sanctioned. I see no basis, however, for "transferring" such liability to the actions taken in response to the emergency, especially where to do so would result in attaching criminal consequences on the basis of negligence to actions which would otherwise be excused.
In my view the better approach to the relationship of fault to the availability of necessity as a defence is based once again on the question of whether the actions sought to be excused were truly "involuntary". If the necessitous situation was clearly foreseeable to a reasonable observer, if the actor contemplated or ought to have contemplated that his actions would likely give rise to an emergency requiring the breaking of the law, then I doubt whether what confronted the accused was in the relevant sense an emergency. His response was in that sense not "involuntary". "Contributory fault" of this nature, but only of this nature, is a relevant consideration to the availability of the defence.
17. A person who
commits an offence under compulsion by threats of immediate death or
grievous bodily harm from a person who is present when the offence is
committed is excused for committing the offence if he believes that the
threats will be carried out and if he is not a party to a conspiracy
or association whereby he is subject to compulsion ...(Emphasis added.)
The rationale for the proviso making the defence unavailable to a member of a criminal conspiracy or association, is the same as that articulated with regard to the common law defence of duress by Lord Morris of Borth-y-Gest in Director of Public Prosecutions for Northern Ireland v. Lynch, [1975] A.C. 653 at p. 670:
In posing the case where someone is 'really' threatened I use the word 'really' in order to emphasise that duress must never be allowed to be the easy answer of those ... who readily could have avoided the dominance of threats nor of those who allow themselves to be at the disposal and under the sway of some gangster-tyrant.
If section 17 and the comments of Lord Morris of Borth-y-Gest embody a notion of "contributory fault" it is not per se on account of the accused's participation in criminal or immoral activity at the time he became subject to threats, nor on account of any simple negligence on his part, but rather on account of the clear foreseeability of his becoming subject to such threats and domination and the consequent conclusion that he was not "really" threatened.
In my view the same test is applicable to necessity. If the accused's "fault" consists of actions whose clear consequences were in the situation that actually ensued, then he was not "really" confronted with an emergency which compelled him to commit the unlawful act he now seeks to have excused. In such situations the defence is unavailable. Mere negligence, however, or the simple fact that he was engaged in illegal or immoral conduct when the emergency arose will not disentitle an individual to rely on the defence of necessity.
RABIE, A., " 'Actiones libera in causa' ", (1978) 41 Tydskrif vir
hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse
reg. (THRHR) =
Journal
of contemporary Roman-Dutch law 60; title noted in my research but
document not consulted; document may not be in English;
ROBACZEWSKI, Corinne, 1973-, Le
rôle de la faute antérieure en matière de
responsabilité pénale, thèse de
doctorat, Lille 2, 2002, dact., 468 f.; directeur de thèse:
Alain Prothais;
titre noté dans mes recherches; cette thèse peut traiter
du sujet. Peut-être que l'auteur peut nous renseigner sur
ce sujet?
"L'objectif de cette
thèse a été de dégager et
d'expliquer le rôle
de la faute antérieure, la
nature de la faute
s'induisant de ce rôle. Alors
que la plupart des auteurs est hostile à la prise
en compte d'une telle faute parce que la culpabilité
ne s'étire pas dans la durée, on s'est
efforcé de montrer qu'elle ne joue à ce
stade qu'un rôle très limité.
Seule la culpabilité réelle et
concrète, nécessaire à la
personnalisation de la sanction,
fait véritablement jouer un rôle à la faute
antérieure.
Le rôle de la faute antérieure
est en revanche omniprésent au stade de
l'imputation, aussi bien positivement, comme une condition d'existence
de la responsabilité
pénale, que négativement, comme une condition
d'exonération de cette
responsabilité. La répression peut
sans doute y trouver son compte; il n'en va pas de
même de la
sécurité juridique...
The objective of the thesis is to
identify and explain the function of
a former offence. We argue that the latter function implies the
qualification of this offence. Most authors rule out the relevance of
taking into account a former offence, on the grounds that the
culpability concept has no inter-temporal character. By contrast, we
demonstrate that the function of a former offence is very limited for
the characterization of culpability. Only effective culpability, which
is necessary for the personalization of the sanction, is argued to
impact the function of a former offence. However, the function of a
former offence is decisive for the delineation of liabilities. This can
apply in a positive sense, as a condition of existence of criminal
liability. This can also apply in a negative sense, as a condition of
limitation of criminal liability. We point to implications in terms of
repressive policy. However, we demonstrate that the function of the
former offence can threaten legal security..." (sudoc catalogue)
ROBINSON, P.H., "Causing
the
Conditions of One's Own
Defense:
A Study in the Limits of Theory in Criminal Doctrine", (1985) 71 Virginia
Law Review 1-63; also published in Albin Eser et al., eds.,
Justification
and Excuse: Comparative Perspectives, vol. 1, Dobbs Ferry (New
York):
Transnational Juris Publications, 1987, ISBN: 0929179226, p. 657;
available
at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=662027
(accessed on 24 March 2008); important
contribution;
SILVING, Helen, "Intoxicants and Criminal Conduct" in Helen Silving,
Essays
on Mental Incapacity and Criminal Conduct, Springfield: Charles C.
Thomas, 1967, xvi, 379 p. at pp. 214-337;
SLIEDREGT, Ellies van, The Criminal Responsibility of Individuals
for Violations of International Humanitarian Law, The Hague: T.M.C.
Asser Press, 2003, xxiv, 437 p., see "The culpa in causa or
'conduct-in-causing'
analysis", at pp. 238-239; "Culpa in causa" for self-defence, at pp.
263-264,
ISBN: 9067041661; copy at Ottawa University, FTX General, K5064 .S53
2003;
__________"Defences in International Criminal Law", Paper to be
presented at the conference Convergence of Criminal Justice Systems:
Building Bridges Bridging the Gap, The International Society For The
Reform Of Criminal Law. 17th International Conference, 25 August 2003-
; available at http://www.isrcl.org/Papers/Sliedregt.pdf
(accessed on 1 April 2008);
SPAIN/ESPAGNE, Codigo penal (espagnol), disponible à http://noticias.juridicas.com/base_datos/Penal/lo10-1995.html; see also http://www.unifr.ch/derechopenal/ley.htm (accessed on 19 May 2006);
SUISSE, Code pénal, art. 19, disponible à http://www.admin.ch/ch/f/rs/3/311.0.fr.pdf
(vérifié le 1 avril 2008); voir aussi l'article 263;
__________ Message concernant la modification du Code pénal suisse (dispositions générales, entrée en vigueur et application du Code pénal) et du Code pénal militaire ainsi qu'une loi fédérale régissant la condition pénale des mineurs du 21 septembre 1998, dans FF (Feuille fédérale) 199 II, pp. 1787-2221; disponible à http://www.domainepublic.ch/files/upload/bot-stgb-at-f.pdf (vérifié le 25 février 2008);
Conformément à la
jurisprudence du Tribunal fédéral et à l’ensemble
de la doctrine 42, le projet va plus loin et déclare
que l’article 17 P ne s’appliquera pas si l’auteur pouvait
éviter l’irresponsabilité ou la responsabilité
restreinte et prévoir l’acte qu’il a commis en cet état.
L’article 17a P vise ainsi
celui qui abolit ou qui réduit ses facultés
d’apprécier le caractère illicite de l’acte ou de se
déterminer d’après cette appréciation,
intentionnellement ou par une imprévoyance coupable. Il n’est
pas nécessaire que le délinquant ait voulu l’infraction
(dol simple), mais il suffit qu’il ait accepté la
possibilité de commettre une infraction (dol éventuel) ou
qu’il ait pu ou dû se rendre compte ou tenir compte du fait qu’en
diminuant ses facultés, il s’exposait au danger de commettre une
infraction (négligence). On pense notamment à celui qui
s’enivre, intentionnellement ou par négligence, alors qu’il
aurait pu ou dû tenir compte du fait qu’il pouvait être
amené à conduire; s’il cause un accident mortel, il sera
puni pour violation de l’article 91 de la loi fédérale du
19 décembre 1958 sur la circulation routière (LCR; RS 741.01) et pour homicide par
négligence.
...
-------
42 Voir par exemple Graven 1995, p. 243 s.; ATF 117 IV 292.